RazorsKiss on the
Christian God as the Basis of Knowledge
Part 8: The “Impossibility of the Contrary”
Originally published on Incinerating
Presuppositionalism on August 26, 2009.
Continued from Part 7.
* * *
In the final section of his opening statement in
his debate with
Mitch LeBlanc over the proper basis of knowledge, presuppositional
apologist RazorsKiss (“RK”) attempted to seal his
case for the Christian god as the proper basis of knowledge by affirming what
presuppositionalism touts as “the impossibility of the contrary.” The
“contrary” in this case is presumably anything different from or contrary to
what Christianity teaches, and the slogan that Christianity is true “by the
impossibility of the contrary” is intended to dismiss all contenders to the
Christian position summarily, with the wave of the hand. Naturally, Christian
apologists who invoke this stance tend to be quite proud of it, apparently
thinking of it as a kind of “nuclear option” which obliterates their debating
opponents in a single blast.
Unfortunately, however, the “impossibility of the contrary” tactic used by
presuppositional apologists typically consists merely of asserting that the
Christian position is true and that all others are false, and involves nothing
interesting by way of legitimate argument. RK’s deployment of “the
impossibility of the contrary” in his debate with LeBlanc is, sadly, no
different from this.
RK begins the final section of his opening statement as follows:
So, now we get to where the rubber meets
the road. If I claim that non-Christians can have knowledge at all, even if it
is faulty knowledge - doesn’t my argument fall apart? I don’t think this is
necessitated. What the Christian position alone can guarantee is any
contribution to knowledge whatsoever.
Clearly RK thinks he’s presented an argument
somewhere in the foregoing sections of his opening statement, presumably for
the claim that the Christian god is the proper basis for knowledge or something
along these lines. I could not find this argument anywhere in his statements.
The final sentence in the above quote – where he makes the bare assertion that
“the Christian position alone can guarantee… any contribution to knowledge
whatsoever” – is typical of what we find elsewhere in RK’s side of the debate.
I’m confident that if you comb through RK’s opening statement as I have,
looking specifically for anything resembling an argument supporting his
position, you’ll come up empty. RK has given no reason whatsoever to suppose
that only Christianity alone “can guarantee… any contribution to knowledge
whatsoever.”
At this point, RK quoted Greg Bahnsen:
However, the presuppositionalist maintains
that the unbeliever can come to know certain things (despite his espoused
rejection of God’s truth) for the simple reason that he does have revealed
presuppositions - and cannot but have them as a creature made in God’s image
and living in God’s created world. Although he outwardly and vehemently denies
the truth of God, no unbeliever is inwardly and sincerely devoid of the
knowledge of God. It is not a saving knowledge of God to be sure, but even as
condemning knowledge natural revelation still provides a
knowledge of God. Thus, according to Biblical epistemology, while men
deny their Creator they nevertheless possess an inescapable knowledge of Him;
and because they know God (even though they know Him in curse and reprobation)
they are able to attain a limited understanding of the world. (Always Ready,
p. 38)
This passage from Greg Bahnsen’s book is unhelpful
to RK’s task, if that task is to validate the claim that the Christian
worldview is solely capable of grounding knowledge. All this passage does is
describe an internal position within the presuppositionalist tradition which is
intended expressly to reconcile what appears to be a contradiction. As such, it
does not bring RK any closer to identifying reasons why anyone should suppose
that knowledge finds its basis in the Christian god. Indeed, everything Bahnsen
states in this quotation assumes the very point in question, thus begging it
outright, if in fact it is intended as a supporting argument for position which
RK has chosen to defend in his debate with LeBlanc. Begging the question on
behalf of the position you’re called to support, is not the recommended course
to take in such a debate.
Moreover, if we look at what Bahnsen states in the excerpted quote, we will
find that what he says is completely arbitrary. If Bahnsen’s god in fact does
not exist, what would keep him from making statements about it in this manner?
Bahnsen claims that the “unbeliever… outwardly and vehemently denies the truth
of God,” but also that he “knows” this god nonetheless. How does he “know”
this? Because, Bahnsen claims, he has “revealed presuppositions,” and that’s
because he is “a creature made in God’s image.” Thus, “while men deny their
Creator they nevertheless possess an inescapable knowledge of Him,” and this in
turn allows them “to attain a limited understanding of the world.” Of course,
Bahnsen had to learn all this by reading the bible, rather than through
“revealed presuppositions” non-believers allegedly enjoy, which simply
undermines the credibility of the very point he’s trying to make here. It is
disingenuous to learn something by reading a storybook and then claim to have
known it directly from a supernatural source by virtue of having been “created”
in the image of a divine being.
The notion of “natural revelation,” to which Bahnsen appeals, finds its
biblical basis in Romans 1:20-21, which states:
For the invisible things of him from the
creation of the world are clearly seen, being understood by the things that are
made, even his eternal power and Godhead; so that they are without excuse,
because that, when they knew God, they glorified him not as God, neither were
thankful; but became vain in their imaginations, and their foolish heart was
darkened.
Presuppositionalists make reference to this passage
from Paul’s epistle to the Romans quite frequently. But drawing our attention
to it does not strike me as very wise, for it affirms a contradiction. It says
that “invisible things… are clearly seen.” But if the things in question are
“clearly seen,” then logically they could not be “invisible things.” If
something is seen, it is visible, not invisible. Moreover, if the “things” in
question are in fact “invisible,” by what means does someone know that they are
there, that they are in fact real, and not imaginary? As the old saying goes,
the invisible and the non-existent look very much alike, and the non-existent
and the imaginary behave very much alike.
The idea here is that the natural world (as opposed to things which are
man-made) somehow “reveals” the Christian god as their creator. As Van Til explains:
All men know God. Every fact of the
universe has God’s stamp of ownership indelibly and with large letters engraved
upon it… All men know not merely that a God exists, but they know that
God, the true God, the only God, exists. They cannot be conscious
of themselves, says Calvin, except they be at the same time conscious of God as
their creator. This general revelation of God stays with man whatever his
attitude toward God may be. When he sins against God, he must sin against this
God whom he knows. Otherwise sin would be sin in a vacuum. Even in the
hereafter, the lost and the evil angels still know God. (Common Grace,
p. 130)
Presumably we’re supposed to be able to look at
anything in nature, whether it is a flower, a piece of granite, a shooting star
or an approaching hurricane, and see “God’s stamp of ownership” on it, since it
is “indelibly and with large letters engraved upon it.” We would simply have to
be utterly blind and stupid not to see this “stamp of ownership” on these
things. Of course, when I look at a flower or a rock, or gaze at the nighttime
sky or observe weather activity, I see no “large letters engraved upon it.” Van
Til might reply by saying that his wording is simply
metaphorical. But this gives away the game: if the indicator of this alleged
“stamp of ownership” which he says is “indelibly and with large letters
engraved upon” everything we encounter in the world is merely “metaphorical,”
then why suppose it’s really there in the first place? Appealing to “natural
revelation” simply begs the question, for this appeal itself rests on
assumptions whose alleged truth is not “clearly seen” in the world, but which
are derived elsewhere. Van Til’s final appeal to
undesirable consequences – “otherwise sin would be sin in a vacuum” – only
broadcasts the dubiousness of this doctrine.
But its dubious nature does not stop there. Speaking of “natural revelation,”
RK stated the following when Mitch LeBlanc questioned him about how he derives
knowledge of his god:
The Created order attests to these things
as well, in a lesser, and more inferential way - but
as I said, that is sufficient merely to condemn.
The admission that “natural revelation” in fact
depends on an individual’s inferences is significant. It tells us that,
contrary to what we read in Romans 1:20-21, that these “invisible things” of
the Christian god which are supposedly stamped “indelibly and with large
letters,” are in fact not “clearly seen” – i.e., not directly perceived
– but in fact projected onto them by the believer attempting to take his
religious teachings seriously. They’re not really there, but he imagines that
they are there, and expects everyone else to “see” them there, just as he imagines
that they are there. This is essentially a concession that Christian god exists
only in the eye of the beholder.
Even presuppositionalists should recognize that inference is not a
“presupposition-less” mental operation, that it builds
upon assumptions which have been accepted prior to working one’s way to the
conclusion of said inference. A truth which is inferred is not a truth which is
directly perceived, just as “invisible things” are not things which can be
“clearly seen.” So the notion of “natural revelation” provides no legitimate
support here. Van Til makes a critical admission in
this regard when he states:
Men must be told that the revelation of
God round about them and the revelation of God within their own constitution is clear and plain, rendering them without excuse. (Op. cit.)
If “men must be told” that what they are seeing
and experiencing “round about them” and “within their own constitution” is “the
revelation of God,” and this “revelation of God” is “clear and plain,” then
what confidence do we have that any of this is true? Typically
presuppositionalists appeal to “natural revelation” to support what they call
“special revelation,” which is “supernatural verbal revelation” (Van Til’s Apologetic: Readings & Analysis, p. 195) from
the Christian god, i.e., the bible itself. Essentially, you’re supposed to read
the bible first, then take what it says and project it onto the reality you
perceive and interact with through your own firsthand experience.
Bahnsen affirms this very point:
Nartural revelation was never intended to operate
on its own without God’s verbal communication as a supplemental and necessary
context for understanding… In that case, man was never – and is not now –
expected simply to observe the natural world or consider his own rational, moral
personality and figure out for himself how they are to be interpreted and how
their truths are to be verbally expressed. (Ibid.)
But even though what Bahnsen says here does not
comport with what the apostle Paul writes in Romans 1:20-21 (Paul tells us that
"the invisible things" of the Christian god are "clearly
seen," and wants this "natural revelation" to condemn everyone
so that "they are without excuse"), Van Til
curiously admits as much himself when he writes:
Man was never left to the study of natural
revelation alone. Natural revelation was from the outset of history accompanied
and supplemented by supernatural revelation. The two were involved in one
another; they were supplemental to one another. They are unintelligible the one
without the other. (The Intellectual Challenge of the Gospel, p. 20)
So much for “the invisible things” of the
Christian god being “clearly seen.” Not only does this claim contradict itself (since
things which are “clearly seen” are not, by virtue of being “clearly seen,”
nonetheless “invisible”), but its reliance on the believer’s biblically
inspired imagination is undeniable.
Moreover, one could claim just about anything using this kind of “reasoning”
which Bahnsen models here. The Blarko-believer, for
instance, could easily apply the same casuistry which Bahnsen gives as a
template for rationalizing his own arbitrary beliefs:
the Blarkositionalist
maintains that the unblarkist can come to know
certain things (despite his espoused rejection of Blarko’s
truth) for the simple reason that he does have revealed presuppositions - and
cannot but have them as a creature made in Blarko’s
image and living in Blarko’s created world. Although
he outwardly and vehemently denies the truth of Blarko,
no unbeliever is inwardly and sincerely devoid of the knowledge of Blarko. It is not a saving knowledge of Blarko
to be sure, but even as condemning knowledge natural revelation still provides a knowledge of Blarko. Thus,
according to Blarkist epistemology, while men deny Blarko they nevertheless possess an inescapable knowledge
of Him; and because they know Blarko (even though
they know Him in curse and reprobation) they are able to attain a limited
understanding of the world.
If Bahnsen can make these kinds of statements about
his god, something which is accessible to the human mind only by means of
imagining it, I see no reason why the Blarko-believer
cannot make similar statements on behalf of his view in like kind. And
apologists like Greg Bahnsen and RK give no objective reason why we should
believe one over the other. Blarko belief is
certainly not the same as Christian belief. Christians worship Christ, not Blarko. But the apologist is claiming that his position is
true because of “the impossibility of the contrary.” If we grant that the
Christian position is possible, what compels us to suppose that the Blarkist position is not also possible? Blank out.
That the Christian defense must appeal to imaginative scenarios in order to
make its points, is evident in what RK says next:
What my claim really entails is that an
unbeliever, trying to start from a position of epistemic autonomy, is like a
child who sits on his father’s lap - and uses that position for the purpose of
slapping his father in the face.
Now we can all imagine the scenario which RK
describes here (he takes it from Van TIl), but our
ability to imagine this scenario does not validate the claim that it is
analogous to the non-Christian’s supposed epistemic plight. Again, RK is simply
assuming the truth of what he is called to prove, that knowledge presupposes
the Christian god. In the second
installment of my analysis of RK’s debate with LeBlanc, I identified the
following facts as the proper basis of man’s knowledge:
1 ) The fact that existence exists: This identifies the realm of objects
which inform our knowledge, answering the question: knowledge of what?
2) The fact that consciousness is consciousness of objects: This
identifies the faculty of awareness possessed by the knower, providing the
meta-answer to the question: How do you know? The subject knows, and what
he knows are the objects of his knowledge. Consciousness gives the knowing
subject cognitive access to what he can know.
3) The fact existence is identity: This is the baseline recognition by a
consciousness that an object is itself, that A is A, not something other
than itself.
4) The fact that existence has metaphysical primacy: This is a baseline
recognition that an object of consciousness exists as itself independent
of conscious activity.
5) The fact that knowledge depends on concept-formation: This is the
ability to form concepts on the basis of objects perceived by the subject. The
method of how the mind forms concepts is explained by a theory of concepts.
To make his condemnation of non-Christian
epistemology stick, RK would have to show how these points are analogous to “a
child who sits on his father’s lap – and uses that position for the purpose of
slapping his father in the face.” Simply asserting that it is so analogous, is
not showing how it is analogous. And when it is realized that this charge must
make use of the very facts to which I have pointed in my proposed alternative
to “Christian epistemology,” it’s quite dubious, to say the least, that we
should expect such scenarios to have any legitimate descriptive merit.
RK then made a statement which can only be taken as autobiographical in that it
tells us about him rather than about the position he deplores so much:
The fundamental disconnect I see in
secular epistemology (and Christians who use that same epistemology) is the
universal lack of a solution from unbelieving philosophy for problems like that
of induction, the one and the many, whether the will is free, and the like.
RK needs to start visiting the library more often,
or do some online shopping. There’s a lot of literature on the topics he
expresses concern for from a non-Christian standpoint. I do not see where he
has dealt with it all, even though he complains of a “universal lack of
solution from unbelieving philosophy” for the problems he mentions. Of course,
I recommend the Objectivist solutions to these problems:
On the problem of induction, see David Kelley’s
Universals
and Induction.
On the problem of universals (“the one and the many”), see Ayn
Rand’s Introduction
to Objectivist Epistemology
On the topic of free will, see Harry Binswanger’s Volition as
Cognitive Self-Regulation
So much for RK’s naked assertion of a “universal
lack of a solution from unbelieving philosophy for problems like that of
induction, the one and the many, whether the will is free…” If RK would like to
discuss these sources once he has studied them, I’d be more than happy to make
myself available for this. But it’s time that he put away childish things, and close the ancient storybook, for it has nothing intelligent
to offer on these matters.
But RK insists that the Christian worldview does have something intelligent to
offer on the philosophical problems he cited:
Christianity has an answer for these -
provided the Christian answers them from Scriptural revelation, and does not
adopt the same principles that unbelieving philosophy does.
It should not be surprising that RK fails to point
to passages in the bible which present solutions to the problems of induction,
the one and the many, whether the will is free, and the like.” That’s because
the bible actually does not address these issues at all, certainly not in any
philosophically valuable manner. The bible was written by philosophical
primitives – an early literate culture trying to survive without the benefit of
rational philosophy, science, and a political worldview recognizing the rights
of the individual. Their concern was not to explore how the human mind works,
but rather to indoctrinate a community of subservience to witch doctors and
priests hiding behind the scarecrow of an imaginary deity known for its
expressions of wrath and destruction. RK is simply deluding himself if he buys
into the notion that the bible addresses these matters.
What makes his position all the more dubious is his stipulation that the
“answers” to the problems he listed are available to the Christian believer so
long as he relies on the content of the bible and “does not adopt the same
principles that unbelieving philosophy does.” Thus the five facts which I
listed above – the axioms of existence, consciousness and identity, the primacy
of existence and a theory of concepts – cannot at all figure in any biblical
solutions to the problems of induction, universals and free will. To make use
of any of these facts would constitute “borrowing” from a non-Christian
worldview. So any solution to these problems which RK could possibly get behind
must deny the fact that existence exists, that consciousness exists, that
identity exists, that existence has metaphysical primacy, and that knowledge is
conceptual in nature. I don’t suppose he’s going to get very far without any of
these facts. But it is true that faith can achieve in a man great feats of
foolishness, so let him try.
RK draws his lines in the sand even deeper:
It is even more so a problem for the
unbeliever - because he doesn’t even have (not always asserted, but always
present to some degree) the epistemological foundation of the Christian.
If “the epistemological foundation of the
Christian” involves a rejection of the facts that existence exists, that
consciousness exists, that identity exists, that existence has metaphysical
primacy, and that knowledge is conceptual in nature, then all
the better for the non-Christian – precisely because he does not have
this reality-denying worldview.
By the way, has RK given any indication how the problems of induction,
universals and free will can be solved without using these facts? Again, his
“impossibility of the contrary” depends on such solutions not only being
possible, but impossibly untrue, and yet we’ve not seen anything but hot air in
regard to the specifics here.
RK baldly asserts:
An unbelieving man has no justification
for his predication.
If the “unbelieving man” acknowledges the five
facts which I specified above, he sure does have “justification for his
predication.” If RK is interested in discussing this, let him come forward, and
address the objections I’ve raised so far in my examination of his debate
against LeBlanc.
RK baldly asserts again:
He has no basis for his use of logical
laws.
Again, if the “unbelieving man” in question
acknowledges the five facts which I specified above, he has all
the basis he needs for his use of logical laws. Those five facts are
the basis of logic. See also my points in this
portion of my response to RK.
RK asks:
After all, wherefore and whence do these
laws get their justification?
From existence, one of the facts which
RK’s position is committed to denying, given his line-in-the-sand drawing
above.
RK offers more faith-based universal negatives about the “unbelieving man”:
There is no area in which his thoughts,
ideas or concepts can be said to be properly grounded. With feet planted firmly
in midair, he asserts his autonomy over his own thinking, and his
self-sufficiency for the use of that thinking!
If you get the impression that RK is simply trying
to convince himself of the claims he’s been asserting and failing to defend
with argument, you’re not alone. But that is the real “meat” of presuppositionalim’s appeal to “the impossibility of the
contrary.” The “feet planted firmly in midair” assertion is an example of the
theistic apologist’s crass habit of projection. He does not need any details
about his rival’s position in order to make sweeping generalizations about it
like this, which means he’s essentially proffering a faith commitment at this
point. The concern here is not to learn and understand what his opponent’s
position may be, but to discredit it regardless of what it is by characterizing
it as simply baseless. But what surer base could there be than the axioms, the
primacy of existence and the objective theory of concepts? And whose position
is better characterized as “feet planted in midair” (whether “firmly” or not)?
Does not the one who endorses utterly baseless axioms about invisible magic
beings residing in an imaginary realm “back of” everything we perceive and the
enshrinement of an ancient storybook full of supernatural characters and men
you’d never hope to have as your neighbors, bear the telltale markings of a
fantasy which preys on an individual’s failure to distinguish the real from the
imaginary? RK accuses non-believers of the very guilt which proliferates
throughout his own worldview.
Speaking of the non-believer’s independence of thought, RK tells us that:
This thinking is dangerous - to the
unbeliever, and to everyone else.
But curiously, RK does not explain how it is at
all dangerous, what threat it poses, and to which values it poses a threat. He
says that
It is little more than, as many assert,
self-worship.
Even if we suppose this is the case, what could RK
possibly have against it? Does his god not worship itself?
Or does it lack entirely an object of worship? If that is the case, then man’s
alleged “religious nature” (which Christians typically assume of man) is not
itself a reflection of his being “created in the image of God.”
Of course, as an Objectivist, I am an unflinching advocate for the morality of
selfishness. This bothers many people, not because they truly think that
selfishness is wrong, but because they want others to accept the notion that
they have a duty to sacrifice themselves to their desired ends. The Christian
believer wants others to worship his god and be willing to sacrifice themselves
to that god, even though it could have no need for their sacrifices in the
first place (it’s said to be “perfect” and “lacking nothing,” “absolutely
necessary” and not “contingent” in any way).
At any rate, accusing people of “self-worship” does not constitute an argument,
nor does “self-worship” – by itself – seem to pose the danger which RK warns us
about. Perhaps he needs to elaborate on this a little more, and fill in the
gaping blanks.
RK confesses that:
If the unbeliever thinks he is the ultimate,
not simply the immediate basis for epistemology - I see no possible way for
that assertion to be justified.
Of course, this is not an argument either. I’m
sure that someone who “thinks he is the ultimate… basis for epistemology” could
come up with some way to make this view seem “justified.” There are many very
inventive minds in the world, and I’m confident that RK hasn’t reviewed all the
possible explanations someone might give for such a view.
But RK would be in error if he assumes that non-belief in his god logically
entails that one “thinks he is the ultimate… basis for epistemology.” While it
is not clear what this is precisely supposed to mean, presuppositionalists (RK
included) offer no reason why someone cannot reject Christianity and yet hold
something other than himself as “the ultimate basis…
for epistemology.”
Again, no argument is offered here.
RK then quotes Greg Bahnsen again:
[The unbeliever] thinks that his thinking
process is normal. He thinks that his mind is the final court of appeal in all
matters of knowledge. He takes himself to be the reference point for all
interpretation of the facts. That is, he has epistemologically become a law
unto himself: autonomous. (Always Ready, p. 46)
Let’s parse this statement point by point.
First of all, suppose that a non-believer “thinks that his thinking process is
normal.” Does Bahnsen think that people should generally adopt a thinking
process that they do not think is normal? Does it bother Bahnsen if a given
non-Christian “thinks that his thinking process is normal”? Speaking for myself
(if Bahnsen will allow it), I think my “thinking process is normal,” since I
govern my thinking process according to objective norms, namely reason and its
method, known as logic. These are not only normal in the sense that they
provide a standard to which my thinking conforms, but also because they are
suited to the kind of consciousness which I possess. Naturally I did not create
my own consciousness or choose what kind I possess. I have it due to causal
conditions that were beyond my control, namely the biological causality which
made my existence a reality and the genetic basis of my nature as a biological
organism. I perceive and have the ability to form concepts on the basis of
perceptual input. These are facts, and my epistemology takes these facts, which
are wholly relevant to the purpose of epistemology and my need for it, into
account from its foundations on up. So yes, if Bahnsen considers my thinking of
my own thought process as normal is a “sin,” I’m happy to confess my “guilt” on
this. Don’t expect it to change.
Bahnsen’s next characterization of the non-believer of course does follow from
the previous one. To suppose that my “thinking process is normal” in no way
necessitates that I think that my mind “is the final court of appeal in all
matters of knowledge.” On the contrary, objective facts are the final court of
appeal. I’m adult enough to know that I am neither omniscient nor infallible,
that I can and sometimes do make mistakes, and that my mistakes do not alter
reality or revise the nature of the objects they involve. Moreover, since
knowledge is knowledge of reality, I defer to reality in my mental activity,
since it would do me no good to substitute what I imagine for what is real. Rational
epistemology equips thinkers for making this fundamental distinction by its
adherence to the primacy of existence. So I suspect that Bahnsen is projecting
here. Since Bahnsen’s worldview is premised on the primacy of consciousness, he
does not have the objective principles by which the distinction between
imagination and reality can be made at his disposal. While Bahnsen would call
his god’s mind as “the final court of appeal in all matters of knowledge,”
since his god is merely imaginary, he is in fact placing his own mind in the
seat of the court judge, telling us what his god can and cannot do, will and
will not do. Pretty easy to make these kinds of statements about something that
is only imaginary. But Bahnsen cannot maintain this kind of pretense
consistently, which is why it only works in the case of his theological claims.
When he’s working with reality and trying to achieve any kind of goal, he has
no choice but to abandon his mystical epistemology and deal with reality on its
own terms. In this way the Christian operates on a mixed epistemology,
proclaiming a specifically Christian epistemology while clandestinely borrowing
from a non-Christian, this-worldly reality in order to get anything of value
done.
Bahnsen then takes a page right out of Van Til when
he says that the non-believer
takes himself to be the reference point for all
interpretation of the facts. That is, he has epistemologically become a law
unto himself: autonomous.
Does Bahnsen produce an argument for this claim? Not
surprisingly, of course not. I have found no argument in any of Van Til’s writings for this claim either. It’s simply a blanket
charge, apparently allowing no exceptions, without citing any evidence to
support it. The only thing which he has to support it is his religious
prejudice, as this is simply an expression of the same.
In fact, what Bahnsen is expressing here is a very narrow understanding of how
the mind works which has resulted from his acceptance of the primacy of
consciousness. This causes him to operate on a false dichotomy, both horns of
which assume a subjective orientation to “all interpretation of the
facts”: either a divine mind is “the reference point for all interpretation of
the facts,” or a human being’s own mind is. Either way, some “mind” must be the
final “law unto itself.” This could only make sense if the mind operates in a
vacuum, denied of awareness of any independently existing objects which could
serve as the ultimate reference point in “interpretation of the facts.” This imaginary
condition, which theism in facts takes seriously, represents the original state
of the mind of its god, as I point out in my blog Before
the Beginning: The Problem of Divine Lonesomeness.
Since it is part of theism that any objects independent of the divine mind were
created by the divine mind in the first place, we need to ask: of what
was the divine mind aware prior to creating any objects independent of itself? Logically, there would have been no independent
objects for it to be aware of at all. The original state of the “ultimate mind”
was a subject in complete isolation from any independently existing objects,
which means: the ultimate condition of divine reality is pure subjectivism.
Hence, we can attribute the false dichotomy implicit in Bahnsen’s declaration
here to the subjectivism
inherent in his god-belief.
Why cannot the facts themselves be “the reference point for all interpretation
of the facts”? Bahnsen does not say. His insistence on the view which he has
presented suggests that he has not even considered such a possibility. This
would be understandable if he were prone to swallow
pretty much everything his teacher, Cornelius Van Til,
asserted, and in the area of apologetics this was the general rule for Bahnsen
for the most part. (If you examine his massive Van Til’s Apologetic: Readings & Analysis, in
which Bahnsen comments on very lengthy excerpts from Van Til’s
writings, you’ll find that in many places Bahnsen prefers to explain statements
by Van Til which were obviously faulty in order to
make them seem reasonable, rather than admit their inherent faultiness. Van Til’s “floorboards” analogy is one example here.)
Is the non-believer then truly “a law unto himself” in epistemological matters?
Not if this means he makes up the laws which govern his thinking process, as an
omnipotent, sovereign deity would presumably be capable of doing. If the
non-believer is one who has adopted an epistemology based on the primacy of
existence, then he conforms his thinking to the facts he discovers existing
independent of his conscious activity. These facts, rather than, say, his own wishes,
provide the standard to which his cognition must conform. So Bahnsen is wrong
to level this blanket charge against non-believers in toto,
and by doing so he only announces his own ignorance of rival epistemologies and
his unchecked bias towards the primacy of consciousness.
Then again, isn’t the subjective paradigm of the divine mind described here
understood as perfection by the Christian, and the Christian himself commanded
to “be perfect” like his god (Mt. 5:48)? Perhaps it’s acceptable for the
Christian to be “a law unto himself” in matters of
epistemology (for many believers in fact act like they are), while for some
reason this is wrong for non-believers.
Again, so much for “the impossibility of the contrary.”
To further solidify his point, RK then resorted to a scenario which is only
accessible to us if we indulge our imagination without adhering to the
constraints of reality:
It is like the famous (and farcical) story
of the scientists who discover how to create life from common dirt! Excited,
they suddenly stop - A voice challenges them - “I doubt you can.” “All right,
then” (say the scientists) - “we will!” As they pick up shovels, they stop
again, as the voice says “No, no. Get your own dirt.”
Now, I can imagine along with RK a group of
scientists imagining that they’ve heard a voice from out of nowhere. I can even
imagine an invisible magic being which produced the voice along with the dirt
which RK says his god created. But to suppose such imagining is representative
of fact is to play a game of “let’s pretend.” Of course, the Christian’s god is
a peculiar one. It is said to have created the universe. But look what it created
the universe with: dirt! Does he really expect me to believe that an
omniscient, omnipotent and all-wise supernatural being rationally chose dirt as
the substance to form the earth?
But RK thinks this story, which he himself admits is “farcical,” is
illustrative of the non-Christian’s epistemological situation:
This is what reasoning is like without the
foundation of God’s self-existence, known through His self-revelation. It is a
man trying to justify his “own” knowledge - when everything he encounters -
including himself, belongs to God. The very idea is utterly absurd.
Note again that RK has not presented any argument
for any of his condemning generalizations about non-Christian epistemology.
This is typical of presuppositionalism. In place of argumentation, the
presuppositional apologist relies on degrading characterizations of rival
positions in order to discredit them. He tends not present an analysis of
actual non-Christian epistemologies as stated by their proponents (and when he
does, he focuses on select quotations which serve as easy prey for his
denigrating intentions), but prefers to issue sweeping opinions consisting, not
of informed assessments of his opponents’ actual stated positions, but of
faith-borne animosity stipulated as sacred truth.
RK calls “reasoning… without the foundation of God’s self-existence, known
through His self-revelation” – i.e., any form of non-Christian reasoning –
“absurd.” But what he misses is the fact that the story he presents as an
illustration of what he calls the absurdity of non-Christian thought, is itself
absurd, because of its assumption of the primacy of consciousness. Nowhere in
his discussion of epistemology does RK ever come close to addressing the issue
of metaphysical primacy (i.e., the question of what is the proper relationship
between the subject of consciousness and its objects), so this point would
likely be lost on him. What RK also misses is the fact that, it is only by
accepting Christianity’s premises in the first place that we could agree with
RK’s opinion that “the very idea” of non-Christian reasoning is “utterly
absurd.” But RK has provided no reasons why one should accept Christianity’s
premises in the first place!
On the other hand, if one does lower his intellect enough to accept
Christianity’s premises, on what basis could he deem anything “absurd”? With
stories about talking serpents, virgin births, walking on unfrozen water,
casting out demons, curing blindness with spittle, and raising the dead from
their graves, what could the Christian possibly take to be “absurd”? And why? On what basis? To assess
an idea as an absurdity, presupposes a constellation of prior worldview
presuppositions, specifically those which have a grounding
in the objectivity of reality, which means: a worldview which adheres to the
metaphysical primacy of existence. It is most ironic when
“presuppositionalists” fail to take into account the presuppositional context
of concepts like “absurd,” which they tend to throw around as if they made
sense in the context of their theistic worldview. But if notions like angels,
demons, and other supernatural beings, the virgin birth, the incarnation and
resurrection of Jesus, and other miraculous elements of the Christian worldview
are not absurd, why suppose the concept has any objective meaning in the
first place? Blank out.
On a rational worldview, i.e., one which is dedicated to adhering to the
metaphysical primacy of existence, theistic ideas are absurd, just as these
tales of miracles and supernatural interventions are absurd. In fact, for RK to
affirm theism on the one hand, and on the other condemn non-Christian reasoning
as “absurd” while using utterly unrealistic scenarios (which RK himself calls
“farcical”) about scientists who, in their efforts to discover how life formed,
hear voices from the beyond commanding them to “Get your own dirt,” to inform
his point, is itself absurd. That RK is not careful to anticipate this in the
defense of his position, seems inexplicable to me,
especially if I am to suppose that he is being guided by the revelations of an
omniscient and infallible supernatural mind.
On the other hand, in the context of a worldview which enshrines the idea of
miracles, what could possibly substantiate the assessment that a mere idea
is “absurd”? Theism is a worldview which insists that the miraculous has
actually occurred in reality, not merely in the imaginations of believers. The
theistic worldview requires men to believe that all kinds of miraculous events
have actually occurred, that the supernatural characters which are portrayed in
its defining stories are real, that there really are angels and demons behind
the objects we perceive moving and interacting in a battle between “good” and
“evil,” etc., etc., etc. If these supposed “realities” are not themselves
“absurd,” how can a mere “idea” be absurd? RK does not explain this. On
theism’s premise of the metaphysical primacy of consciousness, which denies all
objectivity (since it makes everything dependent upon the intentions of
a ruling subject), RK must in fact borrow from a non-Christian worldview
even to invoke the concept ‘absurd’ in any meaningful way.
None of these points occurs to RK as he concludes his section on “the
impossibility of the contrary”:
Since it is impossible to have knowledge
on any other basis, save that of God’s intrinsic nature and self-communication
of the properties of that nature - it is impossible for any human system of
reasoning to have justification at all. In short, Christianity’s epistemology
is the only epistemology possible - because it’s impossible to have any other
coherent, true, and justified basis for thought, perception, knowledge, or
understanding of ourselves, or the creation in which we dwell.
RK has produced no argument to support any of the
contentions he voices here. He has not shown how man’s knowledge depends on the
Christian god; he has not even proven that the Christian god exists. If RK
concedes (as he seems to elsewhere in his debate with Mitch LeBlanc) that
proving his god’s existence was not his intention (RK states explicitly in his
rebuttal to LeBlanc, “I’m not arguing for the existence of God. That is not the
point of the debate.”), then he simply opened a gaping hole in his defense of
theistic epistemology which LeBlanc effectively covered up in his own opening
statement when he effectually demonstrated the irrationality of supposing that
a god exists in the first place. If RK cannot demonstrate the existence of his
god in the first place, then any effort he undertakes to show that his god is
the only basis for human knowledge will inherently suffer from a fatal weakness
internal to his own position. RK is thus exposed as a would-be philosophical
hijacker, someone who has attempted to take over an entire branch of philosophy
through illicit means, but who has failed in that attempt due to his negligence
in sufficiently equipping himself. Indeed, given his aim, it would not be
possible to equip himself sufficiently, so long as rational philosophy is
around to stand guard.
RK’s claim that “it is impossible for any human system of reasoning to have
justification at all,” represents a faith assertion, a claim which he hopes to
convince himself by repeating it. From what he has presented (and from what can
be garnered from the presuppositionalist literature of Cornelius Van Til, Greg Bahnsen, John Frame, Richard Pratt, and others),
it does not represent the conclusion of an intensive, comprehensive survey of
“human system[s] of reasoning” by any means, but rather a view which the
believer hopes is true, but whose alleged truth he cannot demonstrate. If RK
had something solid to present in favor of such assertions, bare and
unsupported as they are, no doubt he would have at least alluded to it in his
opening statement.
Instead of positive argument on behalf of his claims, RK prefers to go with
self-service circularities: “Christianity’s epistemology is the only
epistemology possible – because it’s impossible to have any other coherent,
true, and justified basis for thought, perception, knowledge, or understanding
of ourselves,” etc. His “support” for his position consists solely and
exclusively of repeating that position using different wording. RK provides no
analysis of “thought, perception, knowledge, or understanding of ourselves” which objectively demonstrates their
alleged dependence on the existence and character of an invisible magic being.
He provides no substantiation for the universally negative generalization that
“it is impossible for a human system of reasoning to have justification
at all.” For him even to embark on proving such a contention, he would at
minimum need to conduct a thorough analysis of the Objectivist epistemology,
including its metaphysical basis, its theory of concepts, its adherence to objectivity
and reason, its recognition of the nature of man’s need for knowledge and an
objective process by which he discovers and validates it, in order to have any
hope at all in the faith-assertions he announces here. Since RK has not done
any of this, it can safely be said that his “impossibility of the contrary” is
simply an expression of his own ignorance on the matters which he discusses,
and such ignorance is not a worthy basis on which to premise one’s
condemnations.
In answer to RK’s position, all that needs to be pointed out is the fact that
knowledge is impossible without the ability to form concepts, and that a
comprehensive epistemology needs to account for this ability. There is no
rational basis to contend that human beings do not have this ability, for any
human being attempting to dispute this ability would himself need to possess it
in order to formulate his contentions against it. But in all his discussion of
knowledge, RK never provides his worldview’s definition of knowledge (does he
even have one?) or its understanding of concepts (including an explanation of
their nature, their formation, and their purpose). It may be that R’s worldview
has nothing to say on these matters (if it did, his failure to indicate what
his worldview does have to say on these matters is inexplicable), in which case
his worldview is simply insufficient to have anything worthy to consider on
these matters. This can only mean: the claim that the Christian god is the
basis of knowledge because of “the impossibility of the contrary” is simply
false, and should be rejected without further consideration.
To Part 9.
________________________
Back to RazorsKiss on the Christian God as the Basis of Knowledge